LARA

Differences

This shows you the differences between two versions of the page.

Link to this comparison view

Both sides previous revision Previous revision
Next revision
Previous revision
Next revision Both sides next revision
sav08:complete_recursive_axiomatizations [2008/04/06 16:43]
vkuncak
sav08:complete_recursive_axiomatizations [2008/04/06 16:52]
vkuncak
Line 2: Line 2:
  
 ---- ----
-**Theorem:​** Let a set of formulas ​$Ax$ be a recursive ​axiomatization for a [[First-Order Theories|complete and consistent theory]], that is: +**Theorem:​** Let a set of first-order sentences ​$Ax$ be a recursively enumerable ​axiomatization for a [[First-Order Theories|complete and consistent theory]], that is: 
-  * $Ax$ is recursive: there exists ​an algorithm for checking, given $F$, whether ​$F \in Ax+  * $Ax$ is recursively enumerable: there exists an enumerateion $A_1,A_2,\ldots$ of the set $Ax$ and there exists an algorithm that given $icomputes ​$A_i$; 
-  * $Conseq(Ax)$ is complete: for each FOL sentence $F$, either $F \in Conseq(Ax)$ or $(\lnot F) \in Conseq(Ax)$+  * $Conseq(Ax)$ is complete: for each FOL sentence $F$, either $F \in Conseq(Ax)$ or $(\lnot F) \in Conseq(Ax)$;
 Then there exists an algorithm for checking, given $F$, whether $F \in Conseq(Ax)$. Then there exists an algorithm for checking, given $F$, whether $F \in Conseq(Ax)$.
  
-----+**Proof.**++++| 
 +Suppose $Ax$ is a complete recursive axiomatization. ​ There are two cases, depending on whether $Ax$ is consistent. 
 +  * **Case 1):** The set $Ax$ is inconsistent,​ that is, there are not models for $Ax$.  Then $Conseq(Ax)$ is the set of all first-order sentences and there is a trivial algorithm for checking whether $F \in Conseq(Ax)$:​ always return true. 
 +  * **Case 2):** The set $Ax$ is consistent. ​ Given $F$, to check whether $F \in Conseq(Ax)$ we run in parallel two complete theorem provers (which exist by [[lecture10|Herbrand theorem]]), the first one trying to prove the formula $F$, the second one trying to prove the formula $\lnot F$; the procedure terminates if any of these theorem provers succeed (the theorem provers simultaneously searches for longer and longer proofs from a larger and larger finite subsets of $Ax$). We show that this is an algorithm that decides $F \in Conseq(Ax)$. 
 +    * Because either $F \in Conseq(Ax)$ or $(\lnot F) \in Conseq(Ax)$,​ and theorem provers are complete, one of these theorem provers will eventually halt.  The procedure is therefore an algorithm. 
 +    * If $F$ is proved, then by soundness of theorem prover, $F \in Conseq(Ax)$. ​  
 +    * If $(\lnot F)$ is proved, then by soundness of theorem prover $(\lnot F) \in Conseq(Ax)$. ​ Because $Ax$ is consistent, there is a model $I$ for $Ax$. Then $(\lnot F)$ is true in $I$, so $F$ is false in $I$.  Because there is a model where $F$ does not hold, we have $F \notin Conseq(Ax)$.
  
-In other words, if a complete theory has a recursive axiomatization,​ then this theory is decidable. ​ 
  
-(Note: a finite axiomatization is recursiveTypical axiomatizations that use "axiom schemas"​ are also recursive.)+**End of Proof.** 
 +++++
  
-Conversely: ​if a theory ​is undecidable (there is no algorithm for deciding whether ​sentence is true or false), then the theory ​does not have a recursive axiomatization.+In other words, ​if a complete ​theory ​has recursively enumerable axiomatization, then this theory ​is decidable
  
-**Proof.** +(Note: ​finite ​axiomatization ​is recursively enumerableTypical axiomatizations that use "axiom schemas" ​are also recursively enumerable.)
-Suppose $Ax$ is complete recursive ​axiomatization. ​ ​There ​are two cases, depending on whether $Ax$ is consistent.+
  
-**Case 1):** The set $Ax$ is inconsistent,​ that is, there are not models for $Ax$.  Then $Conseq(Ax)$ is the set of all first-order sentences and there is a trivial ​algorithm for checking ​whether ​$F \in Conseq(Ax)$: always return true.+Converselyif a theory ​is undecidable ​(there is no algorithm for deciding ​whether ​a sentence is true or false), then the theory does not have a recursive axiomatization.
  
-**Case 2):** The set $Ax$ is consistent. ​ Given $F$, to check whether $F \in Conseq(Ax)$ we run in parallel two complete theorem provers (which exist by [[lecture10|Herbrand theorem]]), the first one trying to prove the formula $F$, the second one trying to prove the formula $\lnot F$; the procedure terminates if any of these theorem provers succeed. ​ We show that this is an algorithm that decides $F \in Conseq(Ax)$. 
-  * Because either $F \in Conseq(Ax)$ or $(\lnot F) \in Conseq(Ax)$ and theorem provers are complete one of these theorem provers will eventually halt.  The procedure is therefore an algorithm. 
-  * If $F$ is proved, then by soundness of theorem prover, $F \in Conseq(Ax)$.  ​ 
-  * If $(\lnot F)$ is proved, then by soundness of theorem prover $(\lnot F) \in Conseq(Ax)$. ​ Because $Ax$ is consistent, there is a model $I$ for $Ax$. Then $(\lnot F)$ is true in $I$, so $F$ is false in $I$.  Because there is a model where $F$ does not hold, we have $F \notin Conseq(Ax)$. 
- 
-**End of Proof.** 
  
 Example: the theory of integers with multiplication and quantifiers is undecidable Example: the theory of integers with multiplication and quantifiers is undecidable