LARA

Differences

This shows you the differences between two versions of the page.

Link to this comparison view

Both sides previous revision Previous revision
Next revision
Previous revision
Next revision Both sides next revision
sav08:compactness_theorem [2012/05/06 00:02]
vkuncak
sav08:compactness_theorem [2012/05/06 00:23]
vkuncak
Line 45: Line 45:
 **End of Proof.** **End of Proof.**
  
 +How does this proof break if we allow infinite disjunctions?​ Consider the above example $S = \{ D, p_1, p_2, p_3, \ldots \}$ where $D = \bigvee\limits_{i=1}^{\infty} \lnot p_i$. The inductively proved claim still holds, and the sequence defined must be $true, true, true, \ldots$. Here is why the claim holds for every $k$. Let $k$ be arbitrary and $T \subseteq S$ be finite. Define ​
 +\[
 +   m = \max(k, \max \{i \mid p_i \in T \})
 +\]
 +Then consider interpretation that assigns to true all $p_j$ for $j \le m$ and sets the rest to false. Such interpretation makes $D$ true, so if it is in the set $T$, then interpretation makes it true. Moreover, all other formulas in $T$ are propositional variables set to true, so the interpretation makes $T$ true. Thus, we see that the inductively proved statement holds even in this case. What the infinite formula $D$ breaks is the second argument, that from arbitrarily long interpretations we can derive an interpretation for infinitely many variables. Indeed, this part of the proof explicitly refers to a finite number of variables in the formula.