LARA

Differences

This shows you the differences between two versions of the page.

Link to this comparison view

Both sides previous revision Previous revision
Next revision
Previous revision
sav08:complete_recursive_axiomatizations [2008/04/06 16:51]
vkuncak
sav08:complete_recursive_axiomatizations [2009/05/16 10:47]
vkuncak
Line 1: Line 1:
 ====== Complete Recursive Axiomatizations ====== ====== Complete Recursive Axiomatizations ======
  
----- 
 **Theorem:​** Let a set of first-order sentences $Ax$ be a recursively enumerable axiomatization for a [[First-Order Theories|complete and consistent theory]], that is: **Theorem:​** Let a set of first-order sentences $Ax$ be a recursively enumerable axiomatization for a [[First-Order Theories|complete and consistent theory]], that is:
   * $Ax$ is recursively enumerable: there exists an enumerateion $A_1,​A_2,​\ldots$ of the set $Ax$ and there exists an algorithm that given $i$ computes $A_i$;   * $Ax$ is recursively enumerable: there exists an enumerateion $A_1,​A_2,​\ldots$ of the set $Ax$ and there exists an algorithm that given $i$ computes $A_i$;
Line 9: Line 8:
 **Proof.**++++| **Proof.**++++|
 Suppose $Ax$ is a complete recursive axiomatization. ​ There are two cases, depending on whether $Ax$ is consistent. Suppose $Ax$ is a complete recursive axiomatization. ​ There are two cases, depending on whether $Ax$ is consistent.
- +  * **Case 1):** The set $Ax$ is inconsistent,​ that is, there are no models for $Ax$.  Then $Conseq(Ax)$ is the set of all first-order sentences and there is a trivial algorithm for checking whether $F \in Conseq(Ax)$:​ always return true. 
- +  ​* ​**Case 2):** The set $Ax$ is consistent. ​ Given $F$, to check whether $F \in Conseq(Ax)$ we run in parallel two complete theorem provers (which exist by [[lecture10|Herbrand theorem]]), the first one trying to prove the formula $F$, the second one trying to prove the formula $\lnot F$; the procedure terminates if any of these theorem provers succeed (the theorem provers simultaneously searches for longer and longer proofs from a larger and larger finite subsets of $Ax$). We show that this is an algorithm that decides $F \in Conseq(Ax)$. 
-**Case 1):** The set $Ax$ is inconsistent,​ that is, there are not models for $Ax$.  Then $Conseq(Ax)$ is the set of all first-order sentences and there is a trivial algorithm for checking whether $F \in Conseq(Ax)$:​ always return true. +    * Because either $F \in Conseq(Ax)$ or $(\lnot F) \in Conseq(Ax)$and theorem provers are completeone of these theorem provers will eventually halt.  The procedure is therefore an algorithm. 
- +    * If $F$ is proved, then by soundness of theorem prover, $F \in Conseq(Ax)$. ​  
- +    * If $(\lnot F)$ is proved, then by soundness of theorem prover $(\lnot F) \in Conseq(Ax)$. ​ Because $Ax$ is consistent, there is a model $I$ for $Ax$. Then $(\lnot F)$ is true in $I$, so $F$ is false in $I$.  Because there is a model where $F$ does not hold, we have $F \notin Conseq(Ax)$.
-**Case 2):** The set $Ax$ is consistent. ​ Given $F$, to check whether $F \in Conseq(Ax)$ we run in parallel two complete theorem provers (which exist by [[lecture10|Herbrand theorem]]), the first one trying to prove the formula $F$, the second one trying to prove the formula $\lnot F$; the procedure terminates if any of these theorem provers succeed (the theorem provers simultaneously searches for longer and longer proofs from a larger and larger finite subsets of $Ax$). We show that this is an algorithm that decides $F \in Conseq(Ax)$. +
-  * Because either $F \in Conseq(Ax)$ or $(\lnot F) \in Conseq(Ax)$ and theorem provers are complete one of these theorem provers will eventually halt.  The procedure is therefore an algorithm. +
-  * If $F$ is proved, then by soundness of theorem prover, $F \in Conseq(Ax)$. ​  +
-  * If $(\lnot F)$ is proved, then by soundness of theorem prover $(\lnot F) \in Conseq(Ax)$. ​ Because $Ax$ is consistent, there is a model $I$ for $Ax$. Then $(\lnot F)$ is true in $I$, so $F$ is false in $I$.  Because there is a model where $F$ does not hold, we have $F \notin Conseq(Ax)$.+
  
  
Line 23: Line 18:
 ++++ ++++
  
-In other words, ​if a complete theory has a recursively enumerable axiomatization,​ then this theory is decidable. ​+In short: ​if a complete theory has a recursively enumerable axiomatization,​ then this theory is decidable.
  
-(Note: a finite axiomatization ​is recursively enumerable. Typical axiomatizations that use "axiom schemas"​ are also recursively enumerable.)+Converselyif theory ​is undecidable (there is no algorithm for deciding whether a sentence is true or false), then the theory does not have a recursive axiomatization.
  
-Converselyif theory ​is undecidable (there ​is no algorithm ​for deciding whether a sentence ​is true or false), then the theory does not have a recursive ​axiomatization.+Note: 
 +  * finite axiomatization ​is recursively enumerable 
 +  * typical axiomatizations that use "axiom schemas"​ are also recursively enumerable 
 +  * if $Ax$ is an axiomatization ​for for some interpretation $I$, that is $Conseq(Ax= \{ F \mid e_F(F)(I) \}$, then $Ax$ is an axiomatization ​of a complete theory
  
 +**Corrollary:​** Let $I$ be an interpretation. ​ Then exactly one of the following is true:
 +  * there exists an algorithm for checking $e_F(F)(I)$
 +  * there is no enumerable set of axioms $Ax$ such that $Conseq(Ax) = \{ F \mid e_F(I) \}$.
  
 Example: the theory of integers with multiplication and quantifiers is undecidable Example: the theory of integers with multiplication and quantifiers is undecidable