LARA

Differences

This shows you the differences between two versions of the page.

Link to this comparison view

Both sides previous revision Previous revision
Next revision Both sides next revision
sav08:compactness_theorem [2012/05/06 00:23]
vkuncak
sav08:compactness_theorem [2012/05/06 00:24]
vkuncak
Line 51: Line 51:
    m = \max(k, \max \{i \mid p_i \in T \})    m = \max(k, \max \{i \mid p_i \in T \})
 \] \]
-Then consider interpretation that assigns to true all $p_j$ for $j \le m$ and sets the rest to false. Such interpretation makes $D$ true, so if it is in the set $T$, then interpretation makes it true. Moreover, all other formulas in $T$ are propositional variables set to true, so the interpretation makes $T$ true. Thus, we see that the inductively proved statement holds even in this case. What the infinite formula $D$ breaks is the second ​argumentthat from arbitrarily long interpretations ​we can derive an interpretation for infinitely many variables. Indeed, this part of the proof explicitly refers to a finite number of variables in the formula.+Then consider interpretation that assigns to true all $p_j$ for $j \le m$ and sets the rest to false. Such interpretation makes $D$ true, so if it is in the set $T$, then interpretation makes it true. Moreover, all other formulas in $T$ are propositional variables set to true, so the interpretation makes $T$ true. Thus, we see that the inductively proved statement holds even in this case. What the infinite formula $D$ breaks is the second ​part, which, from the existence of interpretations that agree on an arbitrarily long finite prefix ​we can derive an interpretation for infinitely many variables. Indeed, this part of the proof explicitly refers to a finite number of variables in the formula.