LARA

Differences

This shows you the differences between two versions of the page.

Link to this comparison view

Both sides previous revision Previous revision
Next revision
Previous revision
sav08:complete_recursive_axiomatizations [2008/04/06 16:52]
vkuncak
sav08:complete_recursive_axiomatizations [2009/05/16 10:47]
vkuncak
Line 1: Line 1:
 ====== Complete Recursive Axiomatizations ====== ====== Complete Recursive Axiomatizations ======
  
----- 
 **Theorem:​** Let a set of first-order sentences $Ax$ be a recursively enumerable axiomatization for a [[First-Order Theories|complete and consistent theory]], that is: **Theorem:​** Let a set of first-order sentences $Ax$ be a recursively enumerable axiomatization for a [[First-Order Theories|complete and consistent theory]], that is:
   * $Ax$ is recursively enumerable: there exists an enumerateion $A_1,​A_2,​\ldots$ of the set $Ax$ and there exists an algorithm that given $i$ computes $A_i$;   * $Ax$ is recursively enumerable: there exists an enumerateion $A_1,​A_2,​\ldots$ of the set $Ax$ and there exists an algorithm that given $i$ computes $A_i$;
Line 9: Line 8:
 **Proof.**++++| **Proof.**++++|
 Suppose $Ax$ is a complete recursive axiomatization. ​ There are two cases, depending on whether $Ax$ is consistent. Suppose $Ax$ is a complete recursive axiomatization. ​ There are two cases, depending on whether $Ax$ is consistent.
-  * **Case 1):** The set $Ax$ is inconsistent,​ that is, there are not models for $Ax$.  Then $Conseq(Ax)$ is the set of all first-order sentences and there is a trivial algorithm for checking whether $F \in Conseq(Ax)$:​ always return true.+  * **Case 1):** The set $Ax$ is inconsistent,​ that is, there are no models for $Ax$.  Then $Conseq(Ax)$ is the set of all first-order sentences and there is a trivial algorithm for checking whether $F \in Conseq(Ax)$:​ always return true.
   * **Case 2):** The set $Ax$ is consistent. ​ Given $F$, to check whether $F \in Conseq(Ax)$ we run in parallel two complete theorem provers (which exist by [[lecture10|Herbrand theorem]]), the first one trying to prove the formula $F$, the second one trying to prove the formula $\lnot F$; the procedure terminates if any of these theorem provers succeed (the theorem provers simultaneously searches for longer and longer proofs from a larger and larger finite subsets of $Ax$). We show that this is an algorithm that decides $F \in Conseq(Ax)$.   * **Case 2):** The set $Ax$ is consistent. ​ Given $F$, to check whether $F \in Conseq(Ax)$ we run in parallel two complete theorem provers (which exist by [[lecture10|Herbrand theorem]]), the first one trying to prove the formula $F$, the second one trying to prove the formula $\lnot F$; the procedure terminates if any of these theorem provers succeed (the theorem provers simultaneously searches for longer and longer proofs from a larger and larger finite subsets of $Ax$). We show that this is an algorithm that decides $F \in Conseq(Ax)$.
     * Because either $F \in Conseq(Ax)$ or $(\lnot F) \in Conseq(Ax)$,​ and theorem provers are complete, one of these theorem provers will eventually halt.  The procedure is therefore an algorithm.     * Because either $F \in Conseq(Ax)$ or $(\lnot F) \in Conseq(Ax)$,​ and theorem provers are complete, one of these theorem provers will eventually halt.  The procedure is therefore an algorithm.
Line 19: Line 18:
 ++++ ++++
  
-In other words, ​if a complete theory has a recursively enumerable axiomatization,​ then this theory is decidable. ​ +In short: ​if a complete theory has a recursively enumerable axiomatization,​ then this theory is decidable.
- +
-(Note: a finite axiomatization is recursively enumerable. Typical axiomatizations that use "axiom schemas"​ are also recursively enumerable.)+
  
 Conversely: if a theory is undecidable (there is no algorithm for deciding whether a sentence is true or false), then the theory does not have a recursive axiomatization. Conversely: if a theory is undecidable (there is no algorithm for deciding whether a sentence is true or false), then the theory does not have a recursive axiomatization.
  
 +Note:
 +  * a finite axiomatization is recursively enumerable
 +  * typical axiomatizations that use "axiom schemas"​ are also recursively enumerable
 +  * if $Ax$ is an axiomatization for for some interpretation $I$, that is $Conseq(Ax) = \{ F \mid e_F(F)(I) \}$, then $Ax$ is an axiomatization of a complete theory
 +
 +**Corrollary:​** Let $I$ be an interpretation. ​ Then exactly one of the following is true:
 +  * there exists an algorithm for checking $e_F(F)(I)$
 +  * there is no enumerable set of axioms $Ax$ such that $Conseq(Ax) = \{ F \mid e_F(I) \}$.
  
 Example: the theory of integers with multiplication and quantifiers is undecidable Example: the theory of integers with multiplication and quantifiers is undecidable