LARA

Differences

This shows you the differences between two versions of the page.

Link to this comparison view

Both sides previous revision Previous revision
Next revision
Previous revision
Last revision Both sides next revision
sav08:complete_recursive_axiomatizations [2008/04/06 16:52]
vkuncak
sav08:complete_recursive_axiomatizations [2008/04/06 16:59]
vkuncak
Line 1: Line 1:
 ====== Complete Recursive Axiomatizations ====== ====== Complete Recursive Axiomatizations ======
  
----- 
 **Theorem:​** Let a set of first-order sentences $Ax$ be a recursively enumerable axiomatization for a [[First-Order Theories|complete and consistent theory]], that is: **Theorem:​** Let a set of first-order sentences $Ax$ be a recursively enumerable axiomatization for a [[First-Order Theories|complete and consistent theory]], that is:
   * $Ax$ is recursively enumerable: there exists an enumerateion $A_1,​A_2,​\ldots$ of the set $Ax$ and there exists an algorithm that given $i$ computes $A_i$;   * $Ax$ is recursively enumerable: there exists an enumerateion $A_1,​A_2,​\ldots$ of the set $Ax$ and there exists an algorithm that given $i$ computes $A_i$;
Line 9: Line 8:
 **Proof.**++++| **Proof.**++++|
 Suppose $Ax$ is a complete recursive axiomatization. ​ There are two cases, depending on whether $Ax$ is consistent. Suppose $Ax$ is a complete recursive axiomatization. ​ There are two cases, depending on whether $Ax$ is consistent.
-* **Case 1):** The set $Ax$ is inconsistent,​ that is, there are not models for $Ax$.  Then $Conseq(Ax)$ is the set of all first-order sentences and there is a trivial algorithm for checking whether $F \in Conseq(Ax)$:​ always return true. +  ​* **Case 1):** The set $Ax$ is inconsistent,​ that is, there are not models for $Ax$.  Then $Conseq(Ax)$ is the set of all first-order sentences and there is a trivial algorithm for checking whether $F \in Conseq(Ax)$:​ always return true. 
-* **Case 2):** The set $Ax$ is consistent. ​ Given $F$, to check whether $F \in Conseq(Ax)$ we run in parallel two complete theorem provers (which exist by [[lecture10|Herbrand theorem]]), the first one trying to prove the formula $F$, the second one trying to prove the formula $\lnot F$; the procedure terminates if any of these theorem provers succeed (the theorem provers simultaneously searches for longer and longer proofs from a larger and larger finite subsets of $Ax$). We show that this is an algorithm that decides $F \in Conseq(Ax)$.+  * **Case 2):** The set $Ax$ is consistent. ​ Given $F$, to check whether $F \in Conseq(Ax)$ we run in parallel two complete theorem provers (which exist by [[lecture10|Herbrand theorem]]), the first one trying to prove the formula $F$, the second one trying to prove the formula $\lnot F$; the procedure terminates if any of these theorem provers succeed (the theorem provers simultaneously searches for longer and longer proofs from a larger and larger finite subsets of $Ax$). We show that this is an algorithm that decides $F \in Conseq(Ax)$.
     * Because either $F \in Conseq(Ax)$ or $(\lnot F) \in Conseq(Ax)$,​ and theorem provers are complete, one of these theorem provers will eventually halt.  The procedure is therefore an algorithm.     * Because either $F \in Conseq(Ax)$ or $(\lnot F) \in Conseq(Ax)$,​ and theorem provers are complete, one of these theorem provers will eventually halt.  The procedure is therefore an algorithm.
     * If $F$ is proved, then by soundness of theorem prover, $F \in Conseq(Ax)$.  ​     * If $F$ is proved, then by soundness of theorem prover, $F \in Conseq(Ax)$.  ​
Line 19: Line 18:
 ++++ ++++
  
-In other words, ​if a complete theory has a recursively enumerable axiomatization,​ then this theory is decidable. ​ +In short: ​if a complete theory has a recursively enumerable axiomatization,​ then this theory is decidable.
- +
-(Note: a finite axiomatization is recursively enumerable. Typical axiomatizations that use "axiom schemas"​ are also recursively enumerable.)+
  
 Conversely: if a theory is undecidable (there is no algorithm for deciding whether a sentence is true or false), then the theory does not have a recursive axiomatization. Conversely: if a theory is undecidable (there is no algorithm for deciding whether a sentence is true or false), then the theory does not have a recursive axiomatization.
  
 +Note:
 +  * a finite axiomatization is recursively enumerable
 +  * typical axiomatizations that use "axiom schemas"​ are also recursively enumerable
 +  * if $Ax$ is an axiomatization for for some interpretation $I$, that is $Conseq(Ax) = \{ F \mid e_F(F)(I) \}$, then $Ax$ is an axiomatization of a complete theory
 +
 +**Corrollary:​** Let $I$ be an interpretation. ​ Then exactly one of the following is true:
 +  * there exists an algorithm for checking $e_F(F)(I)$
 +  * there is no enumerable set of axioms $Ax$ such that $Conseq(Ax) = \{ F \mid e_F(I) \}$.
  
 Example: the theory of integers with multiplication and quantifiers is undecidable Example: the theory of integers with multiplication and quantifiers is undecidable