LARA

Differences

This shows you the differences between two versions of the page.

Link to this comparison view

Both sides previous revision Previous revision
Next revision
Previous revision
Next revision Both sides next revision
sav08:compactness_theorem [2012/05/06 00:23]
vkuncak
sav08:compactness_theorem [2012/05/06 00:24]
vkuncak
Line 34: Line 34:
 \] \]
 We next show by induction the following. We next show by induction the following.
 +
 +FIRST PART.
  
 Claim: For every non-negative integer $k$, every finite subset $T \subseteq S$ has a $v_1,​\ldots,​v_k$-interpretation $I$ such that $I \models T$. Claim: For every non-negative integer $k$, every finite subset $T \subseteq S$ has a $v_1,​\ldots,​v_k$-interpretation $I$ such that $I \models T$.
Line 41: Line 43:
 Inductive step: Assume the claim for $k$: every finite subset $T \subseteq S$ has a $v_1,​\ldots,​v_k$-interpretation $I$ such that $I \models T$, we show that the statement holds for $k+1$. ​ If $v_{k+1}={\it false}$, the inductive statement holds by definition of $v_{k+1}$. ​ Let $v_{k+1}={\it true}$. ​  Then by definition of $v_{k+1}$, there exists a finite set $A \subseteq S$ that has no $v_1,​\ldots,​v_k,​{\it false}$ interpretation. ​ We wish to show that every finite set $B \subseteq T$ has a $v_1,​\ldots,​v_k,​{\it true}$ interpretation such that $I \models B$.  Take any such set $B$.  Consider the set $A \cup B$.  This is a finite set, so by inductive hypothesis, it has a $v_1,​\ldots,​v_k$-interpretation $I$.  Because $I \models A$ which has no $v_1,​\ldots,​v_k,​{\it false}$-interpretation,​ we have $I(p_{k+1})={\it true}$. Therefore, $I$ is a $v_1,​\ldots,​v_k,​{\it true}$-interpretation for $A \cup B$, and therefore for $B$.  This completes the inductive proof. Inductive step: Assume the claim for $k$: every finite subset $T \subseteq S$ has a $v_1,​\ldots,​v_k$-interpretation $I$ such that $I \models T$, we show that the statement holds for $k+1$. ​ If $v_{k+1}={\it false}$, the inductive statement holds by definition of $v_{k+1}$. ​ Let $v_{k+1}={\it true}$. ​  Then by definition of $v_{k+1}$, there exists a finite set $A \subseteq S$ that has no $v_1,​\ldots,​v_k,​{\it false}$ interpretation. ​ We wish to show that every finite set $B \subseteq T$ has a $v_1,​\ldots,​v_k,​{\it true}$ interpretation such that $I \models B$.  Take any such set $B$.  Consider the set $A \cup B$.  This is a finite set, so by inductive hypothesis, it has a $v_1,​\ldots,​v_k$-interpretation $I$.  Because $I \models A$ which has no $v_1,​\ldots,​v_k,​{\it false}$-interpretation,​ we have $I(p_{k+1})={\it true}$. Therefore, $I$ is a $v_1,​\ldots,​v_k,​{\it true}$-interpretation for $A \cup B$, and therefore for $B$.  This completes the inductive proof.
  
-We finally show that $I^* \models S$.  Let $F \in S$.  Let $FV(F) = \{p_{i_1},​\ldots,​p_{i_k} \}$ and $M = \max(i_1,​\ldots,​i_k)$. Then $FV(F) \subseteq \{p_1,​\ldots,​p_M\}$. ​ The set $\{F\}$ is finite, so, by the Claim, it has a $v_1,​\ldots,​v_M$-interpretation $I$ such that $I \models F$.  Because $I^*$ is also a $v_1,​\ldots,​v_M$-interpretation,​ we have $I^* \models F$.+SECOND PART. We finally show that $I^* \models S$.  Let $F \in S$.  Let $FV(F) = \{p_{i_1},​\ldots,​p_{i_k} \}$ and $M = \max(i_1,​\ldots,​i_k)$. Then $FV(F) \subseteq \{p_1,​\ldots,​p_M\}$. ​ The set $\{F\}$ is finite, so, by the Claim, it has a $v_1,​\ldots,​v_M$-interpretation $I$ such that $I \models F$.  Because $I^*$ is also a $v_1,​\ldots,​v_M$-interpretation,​ we have $I^* \models F$.
  
 **End of Proof.** **End of Proof.**
Line 49: Line 51:
    m = \max(k, \max \{i \mid p_i \in T \})    m = \max(k, \max \{i \mid p_i \in T \})
 \] \]
-Then consider interpretation that assigns to true all $p_j$ for $j \le m$ and sets the rest to false. Such interpretation makes $D$ true, so if it is in the set $T$, then interpretation makes it true. Moreover, all other formulas in $T$ are propositional variables set to true, so the interpretation makes $T$ true. Thus, we see that the inductively proved statement holds even in this case. What the infinite formula $D$ breaks is the second ​argumentthat from arbitrarily long interpretations ​we can derive an interpretation for infinitely many variables. Indeed, this part of the proof explicitly refers to a finite number of variables in the formula.+Then consider interpretation that assigns to true all $p_j$ for $j \le m$ and sets the rest to false. Such interpretation makes $D$ true, so if it is in the set $T$, then interpretation makes it true. Moreover, all other formulas in $T$ are propositional variables set to true, so the interpretation makes $T$ true. Thus, we see that the inductively proved statement holds even in this case. What the infinite formula $D$ breaks is the second ​part, which, from the existence of interpretations that agree on an arbitrarily long finite prefix ​we can derive an interpretation for infinitely many variables. Indeed, this part of the proof explicitly refers to a finite number of variables in the formula.